The strength of weak embodiment
.
La teoría de la cognición corporeizada se separa de una ontología cartesiana basada en el sistema modular. Las ventajas del enfoque de la corporeización son: a) enraiza la cognición en la experiencia modal, b) está en armonía con una filosofía materialista de la mente (materialismo emergente), y c) está respaldada por la investigación experimental en varios campos. Sin embargo, la corporeización todavía debe dar cuenta de las abstracciones, los malentendidos teóricos (representación vs. no representación) y los hallazgos neurocientíficos que desafían la relevancia de las propiedades sensoriomotoras en los procesos cognitivos. Mientras que la versión fuerte de la corporeización se ve seriamente desafiada por los retos conceptuales y fisiológ... Ver más
2011-2084
2011-7922
11
2018-09-01
77
85
http://purl.org/coar/access_right/c_abf2
info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccess
International Journal of Psychological Research - 2018
id |
metarevistapublica_unisanbuenaventura_internationaljournalofpsychologicalresearch_21-article-3420 |
---|---|
record_format |
ojs |
spelling |
The strength of weak embodiment sistema modular Artículo de revista Embodiment materialismo emergente corporeización correspondencia intermodal. La teoría de la cognición corporeizada se separa de una ontología cartesiana basada en el sistema modular. Las ventajas del enfoque de la corporeización son: a) enraiza la cognición en la experiencia modal, b) está en armonía con una filosofía materialista de la mente (materialismo emergente), y c) está respaldada por la investigación experimental en varios campos. Sin embargo, la corporeización todavía debe dar cuenta de las abstracciones, los malentendidos teóricos (representación vs. no representación) y los hallazgos neurocientíficos que desafían la relevancia de las propiedades sensoriomotoras en los procesos cognitivos. Mientras que la versión fuerte de la corporeización se ve seriamente desafiada por los retos conceptuales y fisiológicos, su versión débil es respaldada por evidencia convincente. Sugerimos que la investigación futura se centre en las bases psicofisiológicas de la cognición corporeizada y redirija los esfuerzos hacia el campo de la correspondencia intermodal. The strength of weak embodiment Gentsch, A., Weber, A., Synofzik, M., Vosgerau, G., & Schütz-Bosbach, S. (2016). Towards a common framework of grounded action cognition: Relating motor control, perception and cognition. Cognition, 146, 81–89. Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). The metaphorical structure of the human conceptual system. Cognitive Science, 4(2), 195–208. Lakoff, G. (2014). Mapping the brain’s metaphor circuitry: Metaphorical thought in everyday reason. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 958. doi:doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00958 James, W. (1894). Discussion: The physical basis of emotion. Psychological Review, 1(5), 516. Hume, D. (1904). An enquiry concerning human understanding (T. K. Paul, Ed.). Open Court Publishing. Harnad, S. (1990). The symbol grounding problem. Physica D: Nonlinear Phenomena, 42(1-3), 335–346. Gover, M. (1996). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience (book). Mind, Culture, and Activity, 3(4), 295–299. Goldman, A. (2012). A moderate approach to embodied cognitive science. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(1), 71–88. Goldinger, S., Papesh, M., Barnhart, A., Hansen, W., & Hout, M. (2016). The poverty of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 23(4), 959–978. Glenberg, A. (2015). Few believe the world is flat: How embodiment is changing the scientific understanding of cognition. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology/Revue canadienne de psychologie expérimentale, 69(2), 165–171. Gibson, J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Gibbs, R. (2006). Embodiment and cognitive science. New York: Cambridge University Press. Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. MIT Press. Fodor, J., & Pylyshyn, Z. (1981). How direct is visual perception?: Some reflections on Gibson’s ecological approach (Vision and Mind. Cambridge ed.; A. Noë, Ed.). MA: MIT Press. Gallese, V., & Lakoff, G. (2005). The brain’s concepts: The role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual knowledge. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22(3-4), 455–479. Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain, 119(2), 593–609. Dennett, D. (1991). The future of folk psychology: Intentionality and cognitive science. In (pp. 135–148). Eskine, K., Kacinik, N., & Prinz, J. (2011). A bad taste in the mouth: Gustatory disgust influences moral judgment. Psychological Science, 22(3), 295–299. Longo, M., Schüür, F., Kammers, M., Tsakiris, M., & Haggard, P. (2008). What is embodiment? A psychometric approach. Cognition, 107 (3), 978–998. Evans, K. K., & Treisman, A. (2009). Natural crossmodal mappings between visual and auditory features. Journal of Vision, 10(1), 6–6. Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. Harvard University Press. Gallese, V. (2003). The manifold nature of interpersonal relations: the quest for a common mechanism. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 358(1431), 517–528. Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Clarendon Press. Gallace, A., & Spence, C. (2006). Multisensory synesthetic interactions in the speeded classification of visual size. Perception & Psychophysics, 68(7), 1191–1203. Frith, C., & Dolan, R. (1996). The role of the prefrontal cortex in higher cognitive functions. Cognitive Brain Research, 5(1-2), 175–181. Freund, P., Friston, K., Thompson, A., Stephan, K., Ashburner, J., Bach, D., … others (2016). Embodied neurology: an integrative framework for neurological disorders. Brain, 139(6), 1855–1861. Lakoff, G., & Núñez, R. (2000). Where mathematics comes from: How the embodied mind brings mathematics into being. Basic Books. Margolies, S., & Crawford, L. (2008). Event valence and spatial metaphors of time. Cognition and Emotion, 22(7), 1401–1414. Mahon, B. (2015). The burden of embodied cognition. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology/Revue canadienne de psychologie expérimentale, 69(2), 172. Sigala, N., Gabbiani, F., & Logothetis, N. K. (2002). Visual categorization and object representation in monkeys and humans. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 14(2), 187–198. Text http://purl.org/coar/access_right/c_abf2 info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccess http://purl.org/coar/version/c_970fb48d4fbd8a85 info:eu-repo/semantics/publishedVersion http://purl.org/coar/resource_type/c_6501 info:eu-repo/semantics/article Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 9(4), 625–636. Vigliocco, G., Vinson, D., Lewis, W., & Garrett, M. (2004). Representing the meanings of object and action words: The featural and unitary semantic space hypothesis. Cognitive Psychology, 48(4), 422–488. Varela, F. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3(4), 330–349. Spence, C. (2011). Crossmodal correspondences: A tutorial review. Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics, 73(4), 971–995. Skinner, B. F. (1977). Why i am not a cognitive psychologist. Behaviorism, 5(2), 1–10. Shapiro, L. (2014). The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition. Routledge. Mahon, B., & Caramazza, A. (2005). The orchestration of the sensory-motor systems: Clues from neuropsychology. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22(3-4), 480–494. Salgado-Montejo, A., Marmolejo-Ramos, F., Alvarado, J. A., Arboleda, J. C., Suarez, D. R., & Spence, C. (2016). Drawing sounds: representing tones and chords spatially. Experimental Brain Research, 234(12), 3509–3522. Price, C., & Friston, K. (2002). Degeneracy and cognitive anatomy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6(10), 416–421. Popper, K. (2005). The logic of scientific discovery. Routledge. Parise, C., & Spence, C. (2008). Synesthetic congruency modulates the temporal ventriloquism effect. Neuroscience Letters, 442(3), 257–261. Montoro, P., Contreras, M., Elosúa, M., & Marmolejo-Ramos, F. (2015). Cross-modal metaphorical mapping of spoken emotion words onto vertical space. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 1205. doi:103389/fpsyg.2015.01205 Meteyard, L., Cuadrado, S. R., Bahrami, B., & Vigliocco, G. (2012). Coming of age: A review of embodiment and the neuroscience of semantics. Cortex, 48(7), 788–804. Merritt, D., Casasanto, D., & Brannon, E. M. (2010). Do monkeys think in metaphors? Representations of space and time in monkeys and humans. Cognition, 117 (2), 191–202. Marmolejo-Ramos, F., Khatin-Zadeh, O., Yazdani-Fazlabadi, B., Tirado, C., & Sagi, E. (2017). Embodied concept mapping: blending structuremapping and embodiment theories. Pragmatics & Cognition, 24(2), 164–185. Marks, L. E. (2004). Handbook of Multisensory Processes. In C. S. G. A. Calvert & B. E. Stein (Eds.), (pp. 85–105). Cambrigde: MIT Press. Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19. Makovac, E., & Gerbino, W. (2010). Sound-shape con gruency affects the multisensory response enhancement. Visual Cognition, 18, 133–137. Mahon, B., & Caramazza, A. (2008). A critical look at the embodied cognition hypothesis and a new proposal for grounding conceptual content. Journal of Physiology-Paris, 102(1-3), 59–70. Dahl, C., Rasch, M., Tomonaga, M., & Adachi, I. (2013). The face inversion effect in non-human primates revisited-an investigation in chimpanzees (pan troglodytes). Scientific Reports, 3, 2504. Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). After the philosophy of mind: Replacing scholasticism with science. Philosophy of Science, 75(1), 1–27. Clark, A. (1998). Embodiment and the philosophy of mind. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, 43, 35–51. embodiment Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body and mind together again. MIT Press. Inglés https://revistas.usb.edu.co/index.php/IJPR/article/view/3420 International Journal of Psychological Research Universidad San Buenaventura - USB (Colombia) application/pdf Journal article 2 11 cross-modal correspondence. Agur, A. M. R., & Dalley, A. F. (2009). Grant’s atlas of anatomy. Lippincott Williams & Wilkins. emergent materialism embodiment the modulatory system Marmolejo-Ramos, Fernando Jones, Nathan Gastelum, Melina Khatin-Zadeh, Omid Tirado, Carlos While popular within some cognitive science approaches, the embodiment approach has still found resistance, particularly in light of evidence arguing against strong forms of embodiment. Among other things, the embodiment approach breaks away from the Cartesian ontology of the modulatory system. We claim that the advantages of the embodiment approach are: a) it grounds cognition into modal experience, b) it is harmonious with a materialist philosophy of mind (emergent materialism), and c) it is supported by experimental research in various fields. However, embodiment must still address abstractions, theoretical misunderstandings (representations vs non-representations) and neuroscientific findings that challenge the extension and relevance of sensorimotor properties into cognitive processes. While the strong version of embodiment is seriously challenged by conceptual and physiological setbacks, its weak version is supported by compelling evidence. We suggest future research focus on the psychophysiological bases of grounded cognition and redirect efforts towards the field of cross-modal correspondence. International Journal of Psychological Research - 2018 https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/ Alsmith, A. J. T., & De Vignemont, F. (2012). Embodying the mind and representing the body. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(1), 1–13. Augustine, J., Fitzpatrick, D., Hall, W., LaMantia, A., McNamara, J., Mooney, R., & Williams, S. (2008). Neuroscience. Sunderland, MA. Churchland, P. (1989). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind-brain. MIT Press. Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. US: MIT Press. Chatterjee, A. (2010). Disembodying cognition. Language and Cognition, 2(1), 79–116. Casasanto, D., & Boroditsky, L. (2008). Time in the mind: Using space to think about time. Cognition, 106(2), 579–593. Casasanto, D. (2009). Embodiment of abstract concepts: good and bad in right-and left-handers. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 138(3), 351. Casasanto, D. (2008). Similarity and proximity: When does close in space mean close in mind? Memory & Cognition, 36(6), 1047–1056. Cardona, J., Kargieman, L., Sinay, V., Gershanik, O., Gelormini, C., Amoruso, L., … others (2014). How embodied is action language? Neurological evidence from motor diseases. Cognition, 131(2), 311–322. Bunge, M. (1999). Social science under debate: A philosophical perspective. University of Toronto Press. Bunge, M. (1980). The mind–body problem: A psychobiological approach. Pergamon: Oxford. Bunge, M. (1978). The mind-body problem in the light of contemporary biology (with Rodolfo Llinás). In 16th world congress of philosophy: Section papers (pp. 131–133). Bunge, M. (1977). Emergence and the mind. Neuroscience, 2(4), 501–509. Brown, S., Cromby, J., Harpe, D., Johnson, K., & Reavey, P. (2011). Researching “experience”: Embodiment, methodology, process. Theory & Psychology, 21(4), 493–515. Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47 (1-3), 139–159. Boulpaep, E., Boron, W., Caplan, M., Cantley, L., Igarashi, P., Aronson, P., & Moczydlowski, E. (2009). Medical physiology a cellular and molecular approach. Signal Transduct, 48, 27. Publication Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes (M. Cambridge, Ed.). MIT Press. Borghi, A., Binkofski, F., Castelfranchi, C., Cimatti, F., Scorolli, C., & Tummolini, L. (2017). The challenge of abstract concepts. Psychological Bulletin, 143(3), 263–292. Blakemore, S.-J., Bristow, D., Bird, G., Frith, C., & Ward, J. (2005). Somatosensory activations during the observation of touch and a case of vision–touch synaesthesia. Brain, 128(7), 1571–1583. Binder, J., & Desai, R. (2011). The neurobiology of semantic memory. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(11), 527–536. Beaton, M. (2016). Sensorimotor direct realism: howwe enact our world. Constructivist Foundations, 11(2), 265–276. Barsalou, L. (1999). Perceptions of perceptual symbols. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(4), 637–660. Barsalou, L. (2008). Grounded cognition. Annu. Rev. Psychol., 59, 617–645. 2018-09-01T00:00:00Z 85 77 https://revistas.usb.edu.co/index.php/IJPR/article/download/3420/2929 https://doi.org/10.21500/20112084.3420 10.21500/20112084.3420 2018-09-01 2011-7922 2011-2084 2018-09-01T00:00:00Z |
institution |
UNIVERSIDAD DE SAN BUENAVENTURA |
thumbnail |
https://nuevo.metarevistas.org/UNIVERSIDADDESANBUENAVENTURA_COLOMBIA/logo.png |
country_str |
Colombia |
collection |
International Journal of Psychological Research |
title |
The strength of weak embodiment |
spellingShingle |
The strength of weak embodiment Marmolejo-Ramos, Fernando Jones, Nathan Gastelum, Melina Khatin-Zadeh, Omid Tirado, Carlos sistema modular Embodiment materialismo emergente corporeización correspondencia intermodal. embodiment cross-modal correspondence. emergent materialism embodiment the modulatory system |
title_short |
The strength of weak embodiment |
title_full |
The strength of weak embodiment |
title_fullStr |
The strength of weak embodiment |
title_full_unstemmed |
The strength of weak embodiment |
title_sort |
strength of weak embodiment |
description |
La teoría de la cognición corporeizada se separa de una ontología cartesiana basada en el sistema modular. Las ventajas del enfoque de la corporeización son: a) enraiza la cognición en la experiencia modal, b) está en armonía con una filosofía materialista de la mente (materialismo emergente), y c) está respaldada por la investigación experimental en varios campos. Sin embargo, la corporeización todavía debe dar cuenta de las abstracciones, los malentendidos teóricos (representación vs. no representación) y los hallazgos neurocientíficos que desafían la relevancia de las propiedades sensoriomotoras en los procesos cognitivos. Mientras que la versión fuerte de la corporeización se ve seriamente desafiada por los retos conceptuales y fisiológicos, su versión débil es respaldada por evidencia convincente. Sugerimos que la investigación futura se centre en las bases psicofisiológicas de la cognición corporeizada y redirija los esfuerzos hacia el campo de la correspondencia intermodal.
|
description_eng |
While popular within some cognitive science approaches, the embodiment approach has still found resistance, particularly in light of evidence arguing against strong forms of embodiment. Among other things, the embodiment approach breaks away from the Cartesian ontology of the modulatory system. We claim that the advantages of the embodiment approach are: a) it grounds cognition into modal experience, b) it is harmonious with a materialist philosophy of mind (emergent materialism), and c) it is supported by experimental research in various fields. However, embodiment must still address abstractions, theoretical misunderstandings (representations vs non-representations) and neuroscientific findings that challenge the extension and relevance of sensorimotor properties into cognitive processes. While the strong version of embodiment is seriously challenged by conceptual and physiological setbacks, its weak version is supported by compelling evidence. We suggest future research focus on the psychophysiological bases of grounded cognition and redirect efforts towards the field of cross-modal correspondence.
|
author |
Marmolejo-Ramos, Fernando Jones, Nathan Gastelum, Melina Khatin-Zadeh, Omid Tirado, Carlos |
author_facet |
Marmolejo-Ramos, Fernando Jones, Nathan Gastelum, Melina Khatin-Zadeh, Omid Tirado, Carlos |
topicspa_str_mv |
sistema modular Embodiment materialismo emergente corporeización correspondencia intermodal. |
topic |
sistema modular Embodiment materialismo emergente corporeización correspondencia intermodal. embodiment cross-modal correspondence. emergent materialism embodiment the modulatory system |
topic_facet |
sistema modular Embodiment materialismo emergente corporeización correspondencia intermodal. embodiment cross-modal correspondence. emergent materialism embodiment the modulatory system |
citationvolume |
11 |
citationissue |
2 |
publisher |
Universidad San Buenaventura - USB (Colombia) |
ispartofjournal |
International Journal of Psychological Research |
source |
https://revistas.usb.edu.co/index.php/IJPR/article/view/3420 |
language |
Inglés |
format |
Article |
rights |
http://purl.org/coar/access_right/c_abf2 info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccess International Journal of Psychological Research - 2018 https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/ |
references_eng |
Gentsch, A., Weber, A., Synofzik, M., Vosgerau, G., & Schütz-Bosbach, S. (2016). Towards a common framework of grounded action cognition: Relating motor control, perception and cognition. Cognition, 146, 81–89. Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). The metaphorical structure of the human conceptual system. Cognitive Science, 4(2), 195–208. Lakoff, G. (2014). Mapping the brain’s metaphor circuitry: Metaphorical thought in everyday reason. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 958. doi:doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00958 James, W. (1894). Discussion: The physical basis of emotion. Psychological Review, 1(5), 516. Hume, D. (1904). An enquiry concerning human understanding (T. K. Paul, Ed.). Open Court Publishing. Harnad, S. (1990). The symbol grounding problem. Physica D: Nonlinear Phenomena, 42(1-3), 335–346. Gover, M. (1996). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience (book). Mind, Culture, and Activity, 3(4), 295–299. Goldman, A. (2012). A moderate approach to embodied cognitive science. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(1), 71–88. Goldinger, S., Papesh, M., Barnhart, A., Hansen, W., & Hout, M. (2016). The poverty of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 23(4), 959–978. Glenberg, A. (2015). Few believe the world is flat: How embodiment is changing the scientific understanding of cognition. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology/Revue canadienne de psychologie expérimentale, 69(2), 165–171. Gibson, J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Gibbs, R. (2006). Embodiment and cognitive science. New York: Cambridge University Press. Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. MIT Press. Fodor, J., & Pylyshyn, Z. (1981). How direct is visual perception?: Some reflections on Gibson’s ecological approach (Vision and Mind. Cambridge ed.; A. Noë, Ed.). MA: MIT Press. Gallese, V., & Lakoff, G. (2005). The brain’s concepts: The role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual knowledge. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22(3-4), 455–479. Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain, 119(2), 593–609. Dennett, D. (1991). The future of folk psychology: Intentionality and cognitive science. In (pp. 135–148). Eskine, K., Kacinik, N., & Prinz, J. (2011). A bad taste in the mouth: Gustatory disgust influences moral judgment. Psychological Science, 22(3), 295–299. Longo, M., Schüür, F., Kammers, M., Tsakiris, M., & Haggard, P. (2008). What is embodiment? A psychometric approach. Cognition, 107 (3), 978–998. Evans, K. K., & Treisman, A. (2009). Natural crossmodal mappings between visual and auditory features. Journal of Vision, 10(1), 6–6. Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. Harvard University Press. Gallese, V. (2003). The manifold nature of interpersonal relations: the quest for a common mechanism. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 358(1431), 517–528. Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Clarendon Press. Gallace, A., & Spence, C. (2006). Multisensory synesthetic interactions in the speeded classification of visual size. Perception & Psychophysics, 68(7), 1191–1203. Frith, C., & Dolan, R. (1996). The role of the prefrontal cortex in higher cognitive functions. Cognitive Brain Research, 5(1-2), 175–181. Freund, P., Friston, K., Thompson, A., Stephan, K., Ashburner, J., Bach, D., … others (2016). Embodied neurology: an integrative framework for neurological disorders. Brain, 139(6), 1855–1861. Lakoff, G., & Núñez, R. (2000). Where mathematics comes from: How the embodied mind brings mathematics into being. Basic Books. Margolies, S., & Crawford, L. (2008). Event valence and spatial metaphors of time. Cognition and Emotion, 22(7), 1401–1414. Mahon, B. (2015). The burden of embodied cognition. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology/Revue canadienne de psychologie expérimentale, 69(2), 172. Sigala, N., Gabbiani, F., & Logothetis, N. K. (2002). Visual categorization and object representation in monkeys and humans. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 14(2), 187–198. Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 9(4), 625–636. Vigliocco, G., Vinson, D., Lewis, W., & Garrett, M. (2004). Representing the meanings of object and action words: The featural and unitary semantic space hypothesis. Cognitive Psychology, 48(4), 422–488. Varela, F. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3(4), 330–349. Spence, C. (2011). Crossmodal correspondences: A tutorial review. Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics, 73(4), 971–995. Skinner, B. F. (1977). Why i am not a cognitive psychologist. Behaviorism, 5(2), 1–10. Shapiro, L. (2014). The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition. Routledge. Mahon, B., & Caramazza, A. (2005). The orchestration of the sensory-motor systems: Clues from neuropsychology. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22(3-4), 480–494. Salgado-Montejo, A., Marmolejo-Ramos, F., Alvarado, J. A., Arboleda, J. C., Suarez, D. R., & Spence, C. (2016). Drawing sounds: representing tones and chords spatially. Experimental Brain Research, 234(12), 3509–3522. Price, C., & Friston, K. (2002). Degeneracy and cognitive anatomy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6(10), 416–421. Popper, K. (2005). The logic of scientific discovery. Routledge. Parise, C., & Spence, C. (2008). Synesthetic congruency modulates the temporal ventriloquism effect. Neuroscience Letters, 442(3), 257–261. Montoro, P., Contreras, M., Elosúa, M., & Marmolejo-Ramos, F. (2015). Cross-modal metaphorical mapping of spoken emotion words onto vertical space. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 1205. doi:103389/fpsyg.2015.01205 Meteyard, L., Cuadrado, S. R., Bahrami, B., & Vigliocco, G. (2012). Coming of age: A review of embodiment and the neuroscience of semantics. Cortex, 48(7), 788–804. Merritt, D., Casasanto, D., & Brannon, E. M. (2010). Do monkeys think in metaphors? Representations of space and time in monkeys and humans. Cognition, 117 (2), 191–202. Marmolejo-Ramos, F., Khatin-Zadeh, O., Yazdani-Fazlabadi, B., Tirado, C., & Sagi, E. (2017). Embodied concept mapping: blending structuremapping and embodiment theories. Pragmatics & Cognition, 24(2), 164–185. Marks, L. E. (2004). Handbook of Multisensory Processes. In C. S. G. A. Calvert & B. E. Stein (Eds.), (pp. 85–105). Cambrigde: MIT Press. Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19. Makovac, E., & Gerbino, W. (2010). Sound-shape con gruency affects the multisensory response enhancement. Visual Cognition, 18, 133–137. Mahon, B., & Caramazza, A. (2008). A critical look at the embodied cognition hypothesis and a new proposal for grounding conceptual content. Journal of Physiology-Paris, 102(1-3), 59–70. Dahl, C., Rasch, M., Tomonaga, M., & Adachi, I. (2013). The face inversion effect in non-human primates revisited-an investigation in chimpanzees (pan troglodytes). Scientific Reports, 3, 2504. Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). After the philosophy of mind: Replacing scholasticism with science. Philosophy of Science, 75(1), 1–27. Clark, A. (1998). Embodiment and the philosophy of mind. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, 43, 35–51. Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body and mind together again. MIT Press. Agur, A. M. R., & Dalley, A. F. (2009). Grant’s atlas of anatomy. Lippincott Williams & Wilkins. Alsmith, A. J. T., & De Vignemont, F. (2012). Embodying the mind and representing the body. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(1), 1–13. Augustine, J., Fitzpatrick, D., Hall, W., LaMantia, A., McNamara, J., Mooney, R., & Williams, S. (2008). Neuroscience. Sunderland, MA. Churchland, P. (1989). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind-brain. MIT Press. Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. US: MIT Press. Chatterjee, A. (2010). Disembodying cognition. Language and Cognition, 2(1), 79–116. Casasanto, D., & Boroditsky, L. (2008). Time in the mind: Using space to think about time. Cognition, 106(2), 579–593. Casasanto, D. (2009). Embodiment of abstract concepts: good and bad in right-and left-handers. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 138(3), 351. Casasanto, D. (2008). Similarity and proximity: When does close in space mean close in mind? Memory & Cognition, 36(6), 1047–1056. Cardona, J., Kargieman, L., Sinay, V., Gershanik, O., Gelormini, C., Amoruso, L., … others (2014). How embodied is action language? Neurological evidence from motor diseases. Cognition, 131(2), 311–322. Bunge, M. (1999). Social science under debate: A philosophical perspective. University of Toronto Press. Bunge, M. (1980). The mind–body problem: A psychobiological approach. Pergamon: Oxford. Bunge, M. (1978). The mind-body problem in the light of contemporary biology (with Rodolfo Llinás). In 16th world congress of philosophy: Section papers (pp. 131–133). Bunge, M. (1977). Emergence and the mind. Neuroscience, 2(4), 501–509. Brown, S., Cromby, J., Harpe, D., Johnson, K., & Reavey, P. (2011). Researching “experience”: Embodiment, methodology, process. Theory & Psychology, 21(4), 493–515. Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47 (1-3), 139–159. Boulpaep, E., Boron, W., Caplan, M., Cantley, L., Igarashi, P., Aronson, P., & Moczydlowski, E. (2009). Medical physiology a cellular and molecular approach. Signal Transduct, 48, 27. Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes (M. Cambridge, Ed.). MIT Press. Borghi, A., Binkofski, F., Castelfranchi, C., Cimatti, F., Scorolli, C., & Tummolini, L. (2017). The challenge of abstract concepts. Psychological Bulletin, 143(3), 263–292. Blakemore, S.-J., Bristow, D., Bird, G., Frith, C., & Ward, J. (2005). Somatosensory activations during the observation of touch and a case of vision–touch synaesthesia. Brain, 128(7), 1571–1583. Binder, J., & Desai, R. (2011). The neurobiology of semantic memory. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(11), 527–536. Beaton, M. (2016). Sensorimotor direct realism: howwe enact our world. Constructivist Foundations, 11(2), 265–276. Barsalou, L. (1999). Perceptions of perceptual symbols. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(4), 637–660. Barsalou, L. (2008). Grounded cognition. Annu. Rev. Psychol., 59, 617–645. |
type_driver |
info:eu-repo/semantics/article |
type_coar |
http://purl.org/coar/resource_type/c_6501 |
type_version |
info:eu-repo/semantics/publishedVersion |
type_coarversion |
http://purl.org/coar/version/c_970fb48d4fbd8a85 |
type_content |
Text |
publishDate |
2018-09-01 |
date_accessioned |
2018-09-01T00:00:00Z |
date_available |
2018-09-01T00:00:00Z |
url |
https://revistas.usb.edu.co/index.php/IJPR/article/view/3420 |
url_doi |
https://doi.org/10.21500/20112084.3420 |
issn |
2011-2084 |
eissn |
2011-7922 |
doi |
10.21500/20112084.3420 |
citationstartpage |
77 |
citationendpage |
85 |
url2_str_mv |
https://revistas.usb.edu.co/index.php/IJPR/article/download/3420/2929 |
_version_ |
1823468297744547840 |